QUATTLEBAUM, Circuit Judge:
An alien may seek to avoid deportation by showing a clear probability that, if deported, he will be persecuted because of his race, religion, nationality, political opinion or membership in a particular social group ("PSG"). Relevant here, if an alien claims he will be persecuted because of his membership in a PSG, that PSG must be "particular."
Juan Carlos Amaya, a citizen of El Salvador, seeks to avoid deportation to that country, fearing persecution on account of membership in the PSG "former Salvadoran MS-13 members."
I.
For context, we begin with a brief description of the law governing Amaya's theory of relief—withholding of removal. "Consistent with our country's obligations under international law, Congress has provided that a noncitizen may not be removed to a country" where he will be persecuted or tortured, regardless of the noncitizen's eligibility for asylum. Guzman Chavez v. Hott, 940 F.3d 867, 869 (4th Cir. 2019).
The withholding of removal statute provides relief from deportation if the noncitizen shows that his "life or freedom would be threatened ... because of ... race, religion, nationality, membership in
II.
Turning now to the pertinent facts and procedural history, Juan Carlos Amaya, a thirty-seven-year-old native and citizen of El Salvador, comes before us with a reinstated removal order. Amaya first came to the United States in 2009 to escape the MS-13 gang, of which he claims he was formerly a member. The government removed Amaya to El Salvador in 2012 pursuant to an IJ's removal order after Amaya was convicted of second-degree assault. Shortly thereafter the same year, Amaya re-entered the United States without inspection. In 2017, U.S. Immigration and Customs Enforcement ("ICE") arrested Amaya at his home in Maryland. ICE reinstated Amaya's 2012 removal order pursuant to 8 U.S.C. § 1231(a)(5). Amaya expressed a fear of persecution and torture in El Salvador and was referred to an asylum officer for a "reasonable fear" determination. See 8 C.F.R. § 208.31(b). The asylum officer determined that Amaya possessed a reasonable fear of torture if removed to El Salvador and referred the case to an IJ for withholding proceedings. See 8 C.F.R. § 208.31(c), (e). There, Amaya sought withholding of removal based on his membership in the PSG "former Salvadoran MS-13 members." J.A. 431, 436-38.
At his immigration hearing, Amaya was the only witness to testify. He testified that gang members forced him to join the MS-13 gang in 2003 in El Salvador. Once he joined the gang, he paid them $25 weekly and attended meetings, but he did not commit any crimes for them. He received MS-13 tattoos on his arm and chest, some of which he later covered. Amaya testified that he left the gang in 2004 after his daughter was born and is no longer a member. He told some other members who did not have leadership positions that he was leaving the gang. Soon after, gang members began threatening Amaya. They told him they would kill him if they got the chance, and, if he were to go to the police, they would kill his family.
In 2005, Amaya testified that an MS-13 gang member shot Amaya in the foot. The shooter called Amaya a derogatory name referencing his former membership before shooting Amaya. That same day, Salvadoran police arrested the shooter. Amaya verified the identity of the shooter in custody for police. Shortly after Amaya left the hospital, two gang members threatened him at his home. They shoved a gun in his mouth and broke two of his teeth, threatening to kill him if he testified against the shooter. Because Amaya did not testify, the government released the shooter with a restraining order for Amaya's protection. Gang members continued
Amaya testified that in 2007, Salvadoran police arrested him for killing three of his soccer friends. The police told Amaya a protected witness had accused him. Amaya alleges the police wanted to find him guilty so that they could imprison him with MS-13 gang members who would kill him. The Salvadoran government detained Amaya for over a year awaiting trial. At trial, the protected witness testified that a police officer had ordered him to accuse Amaya, so the judge released Amaya. In the following year, Amaya claims that gang members continued to threaten him and accuse him of betrayal. Amaya then fled to the United States.
After the U.S. government deported Amaya in 2012 following his assault conviction, he remained in El Salvador for about a month. First, Amaya stayed with his brother, but, after a few days, gang members identified Amaya, which he claimed put his brother's family at risk. Amaya then tried to stay with his sister and later his parents, but the same thing happened. After a childhood friend tipped Amaya off that gang members were planning to kill him, Amaya fled back to the United States.
The IJ denied Amaya's withholding claim and ordered him removed. The IJ found that Amaya was not a credible witness and that there was insufficient independent evidence to support his withholding claim.
Amaya timely appealed the IJ's decision to the BIA, challenging each aspect of the IJ's decision. The BIA affirmed in a single-member decision, holding that even assuming Amaya were a credible witness, he did not show that he was a member of a cognizable PSG because his proposed PSG lacked particularity. The BIA endorsed the IJ's analysis, concluding that the PSG is "too diffuse and thus lack[s] the requisite particularity." J.A. 4. Because it disposed of the withholding claim solely on the particularity issue, the BIA did not address whether the PSG was socially distinct. Amaya timely petitioned this Court for review.
III.
At the outset, it is important to note what is not before us. Amaya challenges
A.
Although the particularity requirement does not appear in the statute, the BIA set forth the requirement to ensure that a PSG has "definable boundaries" so that it is sufficiently clear who is in and out of the group. See Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I&N Dec. at 239. In promulgating this requirement, the BIA explained that a PSG "must not be amorphous, overbroad, diffuse, or subjective." Id. Thus, the purpose of the particularity requirement is "to avoid indeterminacy." Zelaya v. Holder, 668 F.3d 159, 165 (4th Cir. 2012). This Court has rejected proposed PSGs that share only "amorphous characteristics that neither provide an adequate benchmark for determining group membership ... nor embody concrete traits that would readily identify a person as possessing those characteristics." Lizama v. Holder, 629 F.3d 440, 447 (4th Cir. 2011) (holding that wealth, Americanization, opposition to gangs and criminal history were amorphous characteristics) (internal citation and quotation marks omitted). By contrast, we have approved of PSGs that are self-limiting. See Crespin-Valladares, 632 F.3d at 125 (noting the self-limiting nature of a family unit).
The parties disagree as to whether "former Salvadoran MS-13 members" satisfies the particularity requirement. The government asserts that the PSG is too indeterminate because it is difficult to ascertain who exactly is a former gang member. It points to Amaya's background as instructive —Amaya does not remember a moment when he officially left the gang, and he never told any gang leader that he was leaving. The government argues this scenario exemplifies why former gang membership is an amorphous description.
Amaya's position, by contrast, is that "former Salvadoran MS-13 members" is sufficiently particular because it refers to a discrete class of persons and has self-limiting components—it excludes all current members of MS-13, all non-Salvadorans, and anyone who has never been a member of MS-13. Amaya thus contends the PSG provides a clear benchmark for who is in the group, therefore satisfying the particularity requirement.
B.
Whether a PSG satisfies the particularity requirement is question of law, which we review de novo. See, e.g., Martinez v. Holder, 740 F.3d 902, 909 (4th Cir. 2014). Nonetheless, this Court gives Chevron deference to an agency's statutory interpretations of vague terms. See Chevron, U.S.A., Inc. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837, 842-43, 104 S.Ct. 2778, 81 L.Ed.2d 694 (1984). Consistently, both
In determining whether to apply Chevron deference here, however, we must consider several preliminary issues. First, the BIA's opinion is a single-member decision. This Court affords Chevron deference when "an agency's interpretation is rendered in the exercise of its authority to make rules carrying the force of law." Martinez, 740 F.3d at 909 (alterations adopted) (quoting A.T. Massey Coal Co. v. Barnhart, 472 F.3d 148, 166 (4th Cir. 2006)). The BIA only exercises its authority to make a rule carrying the force of law when it issues an opinion by a three-member panel or en banc. See 8 C.F.R. § 1003.1(g). If a single-member BIA opinion relies on a precedential panel decision, however, we still afford the underlying interpretation Chevron deference. Espinal-Andrades v. Holder, 777 F.3d 163, 167 (4th Cir. 2015). Although the BIA opinion below is a single-member opinion and thus does not constitute a precedential interpretation, it does rely on a precedential decision that addressed a materially indistinguishable PSG. See Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. 208, 221 (BIA 2014). Accordingly, the principles of Chevron deference would typically inform our de novo review.
Second, however, the government never sought Chevron deference here until oral argument. Normally, we deem a non-jurisdictional argument not raised in one's briefs either waived or forfeited. But this Court in Sierra Club v. United States Department of the Interior, suggested that standards of review cannot be waived and that Chevron deference is such a standard of review. Sierra Club, 899 F.3d 260, 286 (4th Cir. 2018). Thus, Sierra Club seemingly implies that we should evaluate whether Chevron deference applies, and, if so, apply it, whether or not the parties raise the issue.
That is our situation here. The BIA, and the underlying IJ opinion which the BIA adopted, relied on Matter of W-G-R- in determining that Amaya's PSG lacked particularity. In Matter of W-G-R-, the BIA considered whether a materially indistinguishable PSG from the one here—"former members of the Mara 18 gang in El Salvador who have renounced their gang membership"—met the BIA's previously articulated three-part test for defining a PSG. Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 221-22. The BIA determined the group did not, concluding it was neither socially distinct nor particular. Regarding particularity, the BIA reasoned that the PSG was "too broad and subjective" because it "could include persons of any age, sex, or background." Id. at 221. Because it was "not limited to those who have had a meaningful involvement with the gang," the boundaries of the group were "not adequately defined." Id. at 221. The BIA explained:
Id. The BIA offered guidance, in dicta, that former association with a group will "often need to be further defined with respect to the duration or strength of the members' active participation in the activity and the recency of their active participation if it is to qualify as a particular social group...." Id. at 222.
C.
Assuming Chevron deference applies, our question is whether the BIA's particularity holding in W-G-R- was reasonable. See Chevron, 467 U.S. at 843-44, 104 S.Ct. 2778; Aguirre-Aguirre, 526 U.S. at 426, 119 S.Ct. 1439. An interpretation is unreasonable under Chevron deference if it is "arbitrary, capricious, or manifestly contrary to the statute." Chevron, 467 U.S. at 844, 104 S.Ct. 2778. As evidenced by the word "or," this standard requires us to evaluate the reasonableness of an agency's decision in two distinct ways. Id. In reverse order, one is whether the decision is "manifestly contrary to the statute." Id. Under that test, the BIA's decision is reasonable. Interpreting "particular social group" to exclude "former Salvadoran MS-13 members" is not "manifestly contrary" to 8 U.S.C. § 1231(b)(3)(A). Id.
But under the antecedent requirement set forth in Chevron, which the Supreme Court consolidated in United States v. Mead Corp. and has consistently reiterated, an agency decision, even if not manifestly contrary to the statute, is still unreasonable if it is "arbitrary or capricious in substance." United States v. Mead Corp., 533 U.S. 218, 227, 121 S.Ct. 2164, 150 L.Ed.2d 292 (2001); accord Judulang v. Holder, 565 U.S. 42, 52 n.7, 132 S.Ct. 476, 181 L.Ed.2d 449 (2011) ("[U]nder Chevron step two, we ask whether an agency interpretation is `arbitrary and capricious in substance.'" (quoting Mayo Found. for Med. Ed. & Research v. United States, 562 U.S. 44, 53, 131 S.Ct. 704, 178 L.Ed.2d 588 (2011))); Schafer v. Astrue, 641 F.3d 49, 61 (4th Cir. 2011). That is what we have here. For the reasons set forth below, the BIA's interpretation was unreasonable.
1.
First, the BIA's description of the particularity requirement in W-G-R-impermissibly conflates it with the social distinction requirement. "[T]he particularity requirement flows quite naturally from the language of the statute" and is necessary to ensure there is a "clear benchmark for determining who falls within the group."
Similarly, the social distinction requirement flows from the statute and is necessary to ensure that the PSG is "perceived as a group by society." Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 216 (emphasis in original). Social distinction thus asks whether the "home society actually does recognize that group as being a `distinct' and identifiable group." S.E.R.L., 894 F.3d at 553.
Critically, the requirements serve distinct purposes, and it is important to consider them separately and with integrity to their purposes. Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 214 ("[T]hey each emphasize different analytical aspects of a `particular social group,' and it is necessary to address both elements to properly determine whether the group is cognizable under the Act."). The BIA's articulation of particularity in W-G-R-, however, fails to do this. More specifically, the BIA claims "there is some overlap" between the particularity and social distinction requirements because both "take account of the societal context specific to the claim for relief." Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 214. In general, there is nothing unreasonable about overlap among legal elements or requirements. That happens all the time in the law. But what the BIA calls overlap is actually the incorporation of the social distinction requirement into the particularity requirement. According to the BIA, the particularity question is whether "the group can be described in sufficiently distinct terms that it `would be recognized, in the society in question, as a discrete class of persons.'" Id. (quoting Matter of S-E-G-, 24 I&N Dec. at 584). If that is true, the particularity inquiry requires an analysis into whether the PSG is an identifiable, recognized group from the perspective of the pertinent society. That inquiry, however, is essentially the same analysis the BIA requires for social distinction. This conflation of the particularity requirement with the social distinction requirement not only creates an analytical muddle but also renders the BIA's third part of the PSG test—social distinction—surplusage.
The BIA offers an example that illustrates this point. It explains that "landowners" in an underdeveloped society "could be sufficiently discrete" to satisfy particularity, but it "would be far too amorphous" in "Canada or the United States." Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 214-15. Owning land is no less clear a boundary for group membership in the United States than in any other country. It may be a larger group than in other countries, but it is nonetheless easy to discern if someone is a landowner in the United States.
2.
Second, the BIA's flawed particularity articulation informed its rejection of the PSG in W-G-R-. In the middle of its particularity analysis, the BIA explained that "evidence that the social group proposed by the respondent is recognized within the society is lacking in this case." Id. at 221 (emphasis added). Again, that is the wrong question. Particularity is a definitional inquiry that, like immutability, by its very nature is a question of law. See Martinez, 740 F.3d at 909 (holding that the immutability requirement is a legal question not dependent on evidentiary determinations); see also S.E.R.L., 894 F.3d at 553 (holding that particularity requires "look[ing] at the proposed definition of a social group" to see if one can "determine who falls within it"). Its analysis involves a careful review of the proposed PSG's language to evaluate whether its boundaries are clear. Put another way, is it evident from the group's description who is in and who is not? As such, and in contrast to social distinction, it should not depend on "evidence" or society's perceptions. See, e.g., Pirir-Boc v. Holder, 750 F.3d 1077, 1084 (9th Cir. 2014) (holding that social distinction requires a case-by-case evidentiary inquiry). That is not to suggest that whether a social group is recognized within a society is unimportant. It is. But it is important to the social distinction analysis. It has no bearing on the particularity analysis, and it was legal error, and thus unreasonable, to consider it.
3.
Third, the BIA unreasonably grounded its rejection of the PSG in W-G-R- in part on the fact that it could further subdivide the group in any number of ways—by "age, sex, or background" or by level of "involvement with the gang." Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 221. We fail to see how this reasoning provides clarity to the group's boundaries, as it only points out that there are smaller parts to any whole. What matters is not whether the group can be subdivided based on some arbitrary characteristic but whether the group itself has clear boundaries.
Here, the boundaries of Amaya's proposed PSG—"former Salvadoran MS-13 members"—are clear. On its face, "former Salvadoran MS-13 members" contains several self-limiting features that provide clear benchmarks for the boundaries of the group. First, the reference to a single notorious gang leaves no ambiguity as to how a "gang" might be defined. Second, the group only includes people of Salvadoran nationality, eliminating many people with MS-13 affiliation from other countries. Third, and most significantly, the group does not include those who never joined the MS-13 gang. All those self-limiting features baked into the definition of the group aid in its determinacy.
The government wants us to conclude that because there are gradations in gang involvement, the term "member" is amorphous. But that same argument could be made for any other particular social group and even the other statutorily listed grounds protected from persecution, which the BIA explained "are commonly defined" with enough "specificity" to be "particular." Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at
The government similarly seeks to cast "former" as amorphous because there are varying ways one can become a former member of a group. Appellee's Br. at 15-16 (explaining how former gang membership could include "those who stopped participating in gang activities but never told anyone, those who told gang leaders they were leaving the gang, those who told a few fellow members they were leaving but then stopped participating, those who left the country or area and never told anyone they were leaving the gang, those who left abruptly, [and] those who gradually scaled back their activities ..." (citing IJ order)). Indeed, there are many ways one can become a former member of a group, and those differences may be fatal to an argument that the alleged persecution was on account of membership in the PSG. But they are irrelevant to the particularity inquiry. Further specification of how one becomes a former member does not more clearly define the boundaries of the group; instead, it arbitrarily makes the group smaller. It is already sufficiently clear who is a former member of a group—it is someone who (1) joined the group and (2) is no longer in the group. These terms stand in contrast to other terms this Court has held to be amorphous, like "wealth" and "opposition to gangs," because the terms here provide objective goalposts delineating the boundaries to the group. Lizama, 629 F.3d at 447.
Finally, the government argues the difficulty of applying this proposed PSG cuts against the clarity of the group's boundaries. The government points to Amaya's testimony that there was no specific moment he officially left the gang as illustrative of the group's amorphousness. Appellee's Br. at 16. But that issue goes to whether Amaya met his burden that he was actually in the PSG, not the PSG's particularity. A group can be clearly defined and still have difficult applications, no differently than a clear rule can sometimes be difficult to apply. A difficult application does not turn a clear rule into a vague standard. Take tennis, for example. A tennis court has clear lines that indicate when a ball is in or out. Sometimes, however, it is hard to determine whether the ball landed inside or outside the line, either because it moved so quickly or the vantage point was subpar. The difficulty comes from an inability to see where the ball landed, not from an inability to see the line.
4.
We are mindful that two of our sister circuits have determined that W-G-R- was reasonable, though we are unpersuaded by their reasoning to the extent it is relevant here. In our view, the Ninth Circuit in affirming W-G-R- incorrectly treated particularity as an evidentiary question rather than a legal question. See Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1137-38 ("The BIA's application of the `particularity' requirement ... is reasonable in light of the absence of record evidence demonstrating that Salvadoran society recognizes the boundaries of a group comprised of former Mara 18 members who have renounced their membership, regardless of the length and recency of that membership.") (emphasis added). Particularity is not an evidentiary question—it is a legal question to ensure group determinacy. This Court has always treated the particularity question as such, and we think that is the only reasonable characterization of the requirement. See Temu v. Holder, 740 F.3d 887, 895-96 (4th Cir. 2014) (considering how "bipolar disorder" is a well-defined medical term with identifiable boundaries, as opposed to whether there was record evidence that Guatemalan society recognized the boundaries of those with the disorder). Framing the particularity inquiry as whether there is "record evidence demonstrating that Salvadoran society recognizes the boundaries of a group," moreover, impermissibly blends the particularity inquiry with the social distinction inquiry. Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1137 (emphasis added).
The Eleventh Circuit similarly held W-G-R- was reasonable, but we do not find its analysis relevant here. See Gonzalez v. U.S. Attorney Gen., 820 F.3d 399, 405-06 (11th Cir. 2016) (per curiam). In Gonzalez, the Eleventh Circuit was also deferring to Matter of E-A-G-, 24 I&N Dec. 591 (BIA 2008), a case not relied upon here. In its analysis, the Eleventh Circuit defers to both W-G-R- and E-A-G- together and, in our view, does not meaningfully engage with W-G-R-'s particularity holding, instead "echo[ing]" the analysis in E-A-G-. Gonzalez, 820 F.3d at 405-06 (finding "more persuasive the First Circuit's analysis in Cantarero v. Holder, 734 F.3d 82 (1st Cir. 2013)," a case that pre-dated W-G-R- and analyzed E-A-G-). Therefore, we are not moved by either opinion.
5.
The dissent contends that we have not afforded the BIA appropriate deference. It insists the BIA's statement that "evidence that the social group proposed by the respondent is recognized within the society is lacking in this case" refers to a second prong of a two-part particularity analysis. It claims that the BIA, in addressing particularity, looks first at whether the proposed group's boundaries are sufficiently defined and then at whether the group has sufficient "intergroup similarity" to be discrete. Dis. Op. at 439. It then contends the BIA determined "former Salvadoran MS-13 gang members" failed the second prong. To the dissent, this determination,
There are two problems with this reasoning. First, the BIA has never articulated its particularity analysis in the way the dissent describes it. The BIA did use the concepts of defined boundaries and discreteness in W-G-R. But rather than articulating them as separate requirements, it used those words and concepts interchangeably without any analytical distinction. See Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I&N Dec. at 214 ("`Particularity' chiefly addresses the question of delineation...."); Id. at 221 ("The group as defined lacks particularity because it is too diffuse, as well as being too broad and subjective. As described, the group could include persons of any age, sex, or background.... The boundaries of a group are not sufficiently definable unless the members of society generally agree on who is included in the group, and evidence that the social group proposed by the respondent is recognized within the society is lacking in this case. In this regard, the boundaries of the group... are not adequately defined. The group would need further specificity to meet the particularity requirement."). If the BIA were in fact employing the analysis the dissent suggests, we should at least be able to determine from its opinion in W-G-R- under which supposed prong the PSG lacked particularity. But we cannot, because the BIA had not articulated the test the dissent describes. Instead, the BIA considered whether Salvadorans would view former MS-13 gang members as a discrete group to evaluate whether the definition of the group's boundaries were clear enough. Respectfully, that does not make sense. Whether Salvadorans view former MS-13 gang members as a discrete group has nothing to do with the clarity of the group's boundaries. In addition to not making sense, the BIA's comingling of how Salvadorans view the group with the definition of the group's boundaries shows the BIA did not employ the test the dissent attributes to it.
Second, even if the BIA were to adopt such a two-part test, it would necessarily transform particularity into an evidentiary question of how the society views the proposed group. That does not accomplish anything the social distinction requirement does not already account for, and it needlessly muddles an otherwise definitional inquiry with a fact-based evidentiary question.
6.
The BIA is afforded wide latitude in interpreting vague statutory terms like "particular social group." See Lizama, 629 F.3d at 446-47. Those interpretations must only be reasonable. Id. Our decision today is not intended to hamstring the BIA in its case-by-case decision making process. But it was unreasonable for the BIA to reiterate its three-part test for a PSG and then apply its particularity requirement in a way that disregards and distorts its own test. See Mead, 533 U.S. at 227, 121 S.Ct. 2164; cf. Good Fortune Shipping SA v. Comm'r of Internal Revenue Serv., 897 F.3d 256, 263 (D.C. Cir. 2018) (holding that an agency must engage in a "sufficiently reasoned analysis" that shows awareness
IV.
We grant Amaya's petition in part and remand the BIA's final order of removal. The BIA's determination that "former Salvadoran MS-13 members" lacks particularity is unreasonable, and we thus remand Amaya's withholding claim for the BIA to consider the IJ's other holdings with respect to that claim. But, because the record does not compel a different understanding of the evidence, we deny Amaya's petition for review of his CAT claim. Accordingly, Amaya's petition is
GRANTED IN PART, DENIED IN PART AND REMANDED.
RICHARDSON, Circuit Judge, dissenting:
This case comes down to whether the agency was reasonable in deciding that "former Salvadoran MS-13 members" was not a "particular social group" under the Immigration and Nationality Act. See 8 U.S.C. § 1231(b)(3)(A); Chevron, U.S.A., Inc. v. Nat. Res. Def. Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837, 843, 104 S.Ct. 2778, 81 L.Ed.2d 694 (1984). As the majority rightly explains, our own precedent demands that parties cannot waive application of Chevron deference, as it is a standard of review. See Majority Op. 430-31 (citing Sierra Club v. U.S. Dep't of the Interior, 899 F.3d 260, 286 (4th Cir. 2018)). And Chevron deference applies even when the agency "gives ambiguous statutory terms `concrete meaning through a process of case-by-case adjudication.'" INS v. Aguirre-Aguirre, 526 U.S. 415, 425, 119 S.Ct. 1439, 143 L.Ed.2d 590 (1999) (quoting INS v. Cardoza-Fonseca, 480 U.S. 421, 448, 107 S.Ct. 1207, 94 L.Ed.2d 434 (1987)).
An alien may avoid removal when his life or freedom would be threatened in the country he is removed to because of his "race, religion, nationality, membership in a particular social group, or political opinion." 8 U.S.C. § 1231(b)(3)(A) (emphasis added). Faced with ambiguity over what constitutes a "particular social group," the Board of Immigration Appeals interpreted it to require that "the group is (1) composed of members who share a common immutable characteristic, (2) defined with particularity, and (3) socially distinct within the society in question." Matter of M-E-V-G, 26 I. & N. Dec. 227, 237 (BIA 2014) (emphasis added).
And the agency applies its "particularity" prong by asking two questions: (1) is the group "well-defined" by clear boundaries; and (2) is the group "discrete" in that those within the boundaries form a single coherent group. See Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. 208, 210, 214 (BIA 2014); see also Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 239 (to be particular a group "must not be amorphous, overbroad, diffuse, or subjective"). To answer the first question, we ask whether the definition of the group is linguistically certain in meaning and the boundaries of it are known. See In re A-M-E- & J-G-U-, 24 I. & N. Dec. 69, 75 (BIA 2007) ("The terms `wealthy' and `affluent' standing alone are too amorphous to provide an adequate benchmark for determining group membership."). But the second part, the "discreteness" question, requires a judgment about intergroup similarity: Does the linguistic definition encompass a single group or multiple groups (e.g., adults v. professionals v. doctors v. surgeons)? See W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 214 (a particular social group cannot be "overbroad" or "diffuse," and should have some "limiting characteristic[s]").
Here, the agency determined that Amaya's chosen group, "former Salvadoran MS-13 members," was not sufficiently particular. J.A. 4. The agency relied on its second aspect of particularity: discreteness. In doing so, the agency found that Amaya's "proposed social group[ ] [was] too diffuse and thus lack[ed] the requisite particularity to constitute [a] cognizable particular social group[ ]." J.A. 4.
And because of Chevron deference, we ask only whether rejecting this proposed social group because it was not sufficiently discrete is a reasonable interpretation of the statute. That is, could one reasonably conclude that the statutory phrase "particular social group" requires that the group be adequately discrete? A "particular" group is "a single definite ... set of things or persons, as distinguished from others." 11 OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 270 (2d ed. 1989); see also WEBSTER'S NINTH NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 858 (1984) ("a specific subclass in logic falling under some general concept or term"). This suggests, if not requires, that the proposed group must be a single group with shared traits that distinguish
Two other circuits have agreed that the agency's interpretation is reasonable, as the majority points out. See Majority Op. 435-36 (citing Gonzales v. U.S. Att'y Gen., 820 F.3d 399 (11th Cir. 2016); Reyes v. Lynch, 842 F.3d 1125 (9th Cir. 2016)). Further, even without the benefit of agency guidance, the Ninth Circuit interpreted "particular social group" to require a "cohesive, homogeneous group." Sanchez-Trujillo v. INS, 801 F.2d 1571, 1576 (9th Cir. 1986); cf. Bastanipour v. INS, 980 F.2d 1129, 1132 (7th Cir. 1992) (requiring that the group be "relatively homogenous"). So even accepting that the agency's interpretation is not mandated as the only, or even best, reading of the statute, these decisions support finding the agency's interpretation reasonable.
And reasonable—not clearly right—is all we ask of the agency here: Could the agency reasonably conclude that a social group comprised of former gang members lacks the intergroup similarity to constitute a "discrete" group of persons? Former gang members may include individuals who were in the gang for only a short time, individuals who took leadership positions, individuals who were threatened upon their departure, individuals who aged out of the gang, and individuals who disassociated for religious reasons. See J.A. 67; see also J.A. 307 (describing the ways members can leave an El Salvadoran gang). All those individuals have a different experience, and it would be reasonable to conclude that an ordinary Salvadoran citizen may not consider them a "discrete" subclass of people. Regardless of my own views, it seems at least reasonable for the agency to conclude that such a group lacked particularity.
The majority also accuses the agency of allegedly "conflating" the particularity requirement with the social distinction requirement. Majority Op. 432-33. I cannot agree that what the agency did was so objectionable as to render it unreasonable. As the agency acknowledges, there is overlap in the two requirements. See W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 214. Social distinction looks to whether the group would be "perceived as a group by society." Id. at 213 (emphasis in the original). And, at least under the agency's interpretation, particularity asks whether the group is "discrete" in the society at issue. Id. at 214. Thus, in determining whether a social group qualifies as a "particular social group," the agency looks to the relevant society when evaluating the discreteness component of the particularity requirement and when evaluating the social distinction requirement. The majority, with no apparent legal support, finds this overlap impermissible and would require that these two requirements be wholly separate inquiries. While the majority might prefer that the two inquires not overlap, nothing about the overlap renders the agency's preferred interpretation unreasonable.
Nor is the overlap as significant as the majority suggests. As discussed above, the particularity requirement has two parts: (1) the group must be defined with known boundaries, and (2) the group must be a "discrete" class of persons. See W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec at 210 (quoting Matter of S-E-G-, 24 I. & N. Dec at 584). It is true that in answering the discreteness question, we look to whether the objectively reasonable person in society would understand the group to be discrete. Cf. Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15, 24-25, 93 S.Ct. 2607, 37 L.Ed.2d 419 (1973) (considering community standards as part of an objective test for obscenity). But although they both look to that society, the discreteness question differs from the social-distinction inquiry. The "discreteness" question asks whether someone in that society would find the group to have sufficient shared intergroup characteristics to be considered a single social group, while the "distinction" inquiry asks whether the group is seen as somehow different from the rest of society. See W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 216-17. So, although both focus on the society in which the individual lives, they are different inquiries, and thus it is not "unreasonable" for the agency to require both.
Though a bit unclear, perhaps the majority's error lies in how it tries to redefine "particularity." The majority at times appears to acknowledge that particularity— at least as defined by the agency—has two parts: "The BIA did use the concepts of defined boundaries and discreteness in W-G-R." Majority Op. 437. But while readily discerning these two concepts, the majority faults the agency for not being perfectly clear about it. So the majority decides to collapse the two concepts, limiting "particularity" to "definable boundaries" and leaving "discreteness" to be considered only as a part of the "social distinction" factor. See Majority Op. 433-34, 436-37. Although the agency could have considered discreteness when evaluating social distinction, it was not unreasonable to consider it to be part of the particularity inquiry.
FootNotes
I also question the majority's reliance on the group of "Catholics." Majority Op. 434-35. Under the agency's interpretation, perhaps that group lacks the sufficient intergroup similarity to meet the particularity requirement. But that should not bother us. I do not purport to divine congressional intent, but it is perhaps precisely because Catholics may not constitute a "particular social group" that "religion" is specifically enumerated in 8 U.S.C. § 1231(b)(3)(A).
Comment
User Comments